Where Words Can Be Set Free
Anantanand Rambachan, “Where Words Can Be Set
Free: The Liberating Potency of Vedic Words in the Hermeneutics of Śaṅkara” in Texts in Context, ed. Jeffrey Timm, Delhi: Sri
Satguru Publications, 1997, 33-46.
Pūrva-Mīmāṁsa
claimed that the Upaniṣads did not have an independent purpose. Śaṅkara on the other hand felt that the Upaniṣads were
an integral part of the Vedas. (33)
Pūrva-Mīmāṁsa contend that the knowledge of dharma
and adharma cannot be acquired from any source outside of the Vedas,
while knowledge of other existents, including Brahman could be sought and found
elsewhere. In this way, they ensured the elevated status of the Veda and made
all other literature subservient to it. (34)
Śaṅkara agrees with the Mīmāṁsa contention on the knowledge available
in the Vedas but felt they were doing injustice to the Brahman. According to
him, the two categories of knowledge that are inaccessible to all other pramaṇas (sources of knowledge) and
attainable only through the Vedas are dharma and Brahman (Brahma
Sūtra
Bhāṣya 2.1.6). Both of them are
suprasensible realities and hence lie beyond the reach of ordinary sense. Śaṅkara notes that the first part of the
Vedas give knowledge of dharma (ritual actions and moral practices)
which can be termed collectively as karmakāṇḍa (path of action), while the latter
part of the Vedas reveal Brahman and hence can be termed, jñānakaṇḍa (path of knowledge).
He goes on to provide two reasons why Brahman is beyond sense
knowledge: 1) Every existent is the object of a pramaṇa. There must be an appropriate
relation between the pramaṇa and its object like the ear and sound. But
Brahman is an existent with a unique nirguṇa (attributeless) nature and hence
cannot be known by any pramaṇa.
2) The process of empirical
knowledge involves a distinction between the subject and object, knower and
known. Knowledge presupposes a subject – there must be someone who knows, but
Brahman is the eternal subject. As awareness (caitanya) it illumines
everything even the mind, body and sense organs. Thus, the knower cannot itself
be made the object to be known. Neither can we say that Brahman is both subject
and object since it results in a contradiction. (35-36)
Brahman is not an absolute other,
an unknown. Śaṅkara writes, “The existence of brahman is well known from the fact
of Its being the Self of all; for everyone feels that his Self exists and he
never feels, “I do not exist.” Had there been no general recognition of the
existence of the Self, everyone would have felt, “I do not exist.” And that
Self is Brahman. (Brahma Sūtra Bhāṣya 1.1.1) Such knowledge of Brahman
is only sāmānya jñāna (general knowledge) and not viśeṣa
jñāna (specific knowledge), thus allowing for mistakes and superimpositions
through avidyā (ignorance) to occur.
For this reason, one can speak of Brahman as if it possesses this or that
quality when all the while, Brahman is nirguṇa. In this context, the
function of the words of the Upaniṣads is a help to remove or negate the attributes that are falsely imposed
on Brahman. They help one realize the truth about Brahman. They lead one beyond
the words, beyond the false attributes that are accorded to Brahman to the true
nature of Brahman. (40)
In
order to discover the true meaning of any scriptural passage, Advaita Vedānta
uses the sixfold criteria (ṣaḍliṅga)
formulated by Pūrva-Mīmāṁsa exegetes:
i.
Upakramopasaṁhāra (the beginning and the end) – If the
subject matter at the beginning and end of a text are coherent and congruous
with each other, then the texts meaning is more evident.
ii.
Abhyāsa (repetition) – If themes are repeated throughout the text then it is
obvious that they are important to the text.
iii.
Apūrva (novelty) – If the subject matter of the text can be verified by other
pramaṇas or by experience then something is amiss. The Vedas are supposed to
provide knowledge of things that are beyond human experience and for this
reason they must be valued, respected and followed. However, suppose they provide
information of something worldly and that proves to be incorrect, it doesn’t
reflect well on the text. This could also be extended to mean that one ought to
take as scriptural valid only those parts that go beyond our experience.
iv.
Phala
(fruit) – The purport of a passage is also indicated by the clear mention of an
independent result. This means that if a particular passage mentions its own
independent result, then it cannot be taken to be just another part of a larger
text but must be considered in its own right.
v.
Arthavāda (commendation) This refers to the praise of the subject matter in the
course of the discussion. Occasionally, in the Upaniṣads one finds statements that glorify
the knowledge available in them. These are precise examples of arthavāda.
vi.
Upapatti
(demonstration) – Usage of arguments to clarify and establish the
reasonableness of the subject matter. (41-42)
Advaita holds that through the
application of ṣaḍliṅga,
it can show that the sentences of the Upaniṣads are not inferior to other texts
but have an independent significance in revealing Brahman. (42)
Comments
Post a Comment